For those of you who aren’t familiar with it, this, the trolley problem
is a rather famous thought experiment that goes as follows:
Suppose there is an out-of-control trolley barreling down the
tracks. Ahead of it are five people who,
for whatever reason, are unable to move out of its way, and will be killed when
struck by the trolley. You are standing
next to a switch that can shunt the trolley onto a different track, where one
person is will be killed.
Do you throw the switch?
There are multiple variations on this, of course, because academic
psychologists and ethicists seem to have plenty of time to sit around and come
up with devious twists on these sorts of things. The most famous variation, though, changes
the premise slightly.
Instead of standing next to a switch, you’re standing on a bridge over
the track. Next to you is a person who,
if pushed off the bridge in front of the trolley, would stop it and save the
other five people, but would be killed in the process.
Do you push him?
The answers to this problem have spurred all kinds of research and
attempts at explanation, but they generally fall into two camps of ethics:
deontology and utilitarianism.
Deontology is based around following moral rules. Only actions which follow the moral rule can
be good, and if you’re following the moral rule, than by definition your
actions are good as long as your intent is also good. The means are also an end, basically.
Utilitarianism is based around maximizing utility, which essentially
boils down to maximizing well-being across the affected group of people. This can be summed up by the Vulcan proverb,
“The needs of the many outweigh the needs of the few.”
To help clarify, let’s apply this to the trolley problem. For deontology, we might postulate a moral
rule along the lines of “Take no action causing harm to another person.” In following that rule, we wouldn’t throw the
switch, and we wouldn’t push the person, because both would actively be causing
harm. By doing nothing, the trolley will
kill the other five people, but we haven’t directly done any harm ourselves.
For utilitarianism, the reverse is true. In both cases, we should take the suggested
action: throw the switch and push the person.
After all, sacrificing one person to save five would definitely maximize
the overall utility across the people involved.
Or, if it would resonate better with you, the 10 Commandments are
definitely a deontological system, as are many of the rules laid out in the
Epistles, while Jesus’ second commandment, “Love your neighbor as yourself”
sure seems utilitarian to me. (It’s
still a rule, though, so hang onto that thought.)
(Despite the prior paragraph, for what I hope are obvious reasons, we’re going to focus on
well-being here on Earth, rather than any given possible afterlife.)
Now, naturally, it’s not quite that clear cut in practice. For example, in general, many more people will elect to throw the switch than elect to push the person, probably because of
the degree of separation between their action and the death. Putting a person’s child in one of the roles
can also affect people’s choices. In
short, emotion can overrule reasoning.
Go figure.
And both approaches have their problems, of course.
The most fundamental problem with deontology is defining and agreeing
on what the moral rules are. In
our application to the trolley problem, we could just as easily have postulated
a moral rule like “Always save the greatest number of lives”, and come up with
a completely different result. And, from
a utilitarian perspective, simply following rules regardless of the consequences can seem simplistic, cruel, inflexible, or unreactive to changing
circumstances.
The most fundamental problem with utilitarianism is how you define,
quantify and measure well-being across the population of the problem you’re
addressing. “Kill one to save five”
doesn’t even remotely cover all the aspects to consider. What if the five are all nonagenarians with
no living relatives, while the one is the sole breadwinner for a large family,
for example? When you take
secondarily-affected people, like those in the family, into account, what will
create the greatest utility then? Don’t
forget to take yourself into account, as well; you’re part of this as
well. Is there a precedent being set
that could affect future people? From a
deontological perspective, utilitarianism is ill-defined, relative, convoluted,
or prone to slippery slopes.
So why bring this up?
At the risk of generalizing a bit, I think this split describes some of
the current political divisions we’re currently seeing. To be clear, this is nowhere near a complete description of the problems, and it only addresses people actually acting according to principles, but it's an aspect.
First of all, let’s just look at the definitions of conservative and
liberal (NB: these will not necessarily match to Republican/Democrat; we’ll get
to that in a bit).
Conservative: Holding to traditional attitudes and values and cautious
about change or innovation, typically in relation to politics or religion
Liberal: Open to new behavior or opinions and willing to discard
traditional values; favorable to or respectful of individual rights and
freedoms; (in a political context) favoring maximum individual liberty in
political and social reform
I think the split is pretty clear here, right?
Conservatives are clearly more deontological; their moral rule is
essentially “Keep doing things the way they’ve been done.” Do that, and you’re good.
Meanwhile, equate “freedom” or “liberty” with “well-being” (and I think
most people would do that to at least some extent; I’m equivocating here for a
reason), and those definitions of liberal essentially become the definition of
utilitarianism. And that makes sense; if
you want to reform systems and you’re not out to impose an autocracy or
something, then your guiding star should be trying to find the systems that
benefit the most people the most. People
may disagree about how different systems grade out, but that’s par for the
course.
Now, as mentioned above, the Republican/Democrat split isn’t
necessarily the same as a conservative/liberal split in terms of strict
definitions, and I think most people recognize that. Really, Republicans are “social
conservatives”, while Democrats are “social liberals”, and I think that’s obvious
enough, along with the ethical equivalents, that I’m not going to spell it out
further here. (If it’s not, and I’ve
pulled the dreaded “this should be intuitively obvious” math prof shortcut on
someone here, let me know, and I’ll be happy to elaborate.)
(Also, I’m going to talk here about generic Democrats and Republicans,
rather than anyone in particular who may or may not be operating with good
intentions, holding to their principles, etc.)
The classical construction of definitions on the economic side is that
Republicans are “economic liberals” while Democrats are “economic
conservatives”, but I think that’s not quite right in a couple important ways.
Just to make sure we’re all starting from the same point (if anyone’s
going to argue with a premise, I want the premises to be clear): Republicans,
in general, favor free markets with few regulations, while Democrats favor more
heavily regulated free markets (with a couple special exceptions). While “free markets with few regulations”
does generally fit the “maximum individual liberty” definition of liberal,
“more heavily regulated free markets” doesn’t really fit the definition of
conservative; if anything, it’s just not as liberal. (I’m avoiding the term “illiberal” due to
negative connotations I don’t want to introduce here.)
I would also posit that a laissez-faire capitalistic system is, in
fact, the traditional system here in the US, and has been since the beginning,
which actually makes maintaining it as such the “conservative” approach.
I’m not arguing here that Republicans are “economic conservatives” as
well as “social conservatives”, nor that Democrats are “economic liberals”;
that’s clearly not the case. They’re
just both their own different and conflicting mixes of liberal and
conservative/less liberal.
Now, I’m going to take advantage of all of the caveats I’ve built into
this post so far to define a couple other terms to avoid looking like I’m about
to shift the goalposts wildly.
Utilitarianism comes in two main flavors: rule utilitarianism, and act
utilitarianism.
Rule utilitarianism argues that by following rules that, on average,
result in the most good, you are doing good even if the end result of a given
action is bad. (The classic example is
telling a murderer where to find his targets because lying is bad.) The key distinction between rule
utilitarianism and deontology is why you’re following the rule. Remember that in deontology, following the
rule is good in and of itself, without any care for the net effect on the
well-being of the affected people (remember we’ve ruled out rewards in heaven
for those divinely-inspired rules).
The problem with rule utilitarianism is that it’s not very stable. You either tend to rigidly follow the rules,
which winds up looking a lot like deontology, or you build in so many
exceptions that you wind up with act utilitarianism.
Act utilitarianism simply judges whether an act was good or not by its
results. If the net result was an increase
in well-being for everyone, then it was a good act. If not, it was a bad act. Pretty straightforward (as a definition,
anyways. Not necessarily as a
calculation.)
The problem with act utilitarianism should be obvious: it’s basically
the definition of “the ends justify the means”.
For example, should a surgeon kill one healthy person to harvest organs
to save five other people? The basic
structure of the problem is the same as the trolley problem, but I imagine that
there are far fewer people who would say yes to this question than even those
who would push the person off the bridge.
So why am I bringing these things up now? To me, rather than thinking of economic
approaches as liberal/conservative, I think it’s more useful to think of them
in these ethical terms.
Republicans, I would argue, are “economic rule utilitarians”. They follow rules like “Government should be
as small as possible” and “Taxes should be as low as possible” in the belief
that these rules maximize well-being overall.
And recall that I did point out before that, to some extent, most people
will equate “individual liberty” with “well-being”, so there’s some
justification for this approach.
Democrats, on the other hand, would seem to be “economic act
utilitarians”. They believe that, in
some cases, increased regulation can actually do better at maximizing
well-being/individual liberty. Note that
this doesn’t equate to “Government should be as big as possible” or that “Taxes
should be as high as possible”, it equates to “Government and taxes should be
set so as to implement the desired policies.” Given that sometimes one person’s liberty can
impact another’s in an adverse manner, there’s some justification for this
approach as well.
Do I have a point to all of this?
A few, actually.
First, there’s something here I’ve been hinting at and dancing around,
but which I’ve so far mostly avoided addressing: systems thinking. I haven’t really wanted to touch on it here
because I think it deserves its own post (next week, hopefully!), but the
takeaway here is just that the amount of systems thinking these approaches take
forms something of a spectrum. The more
you have to judge the effects of an act and quantify changes to well-being, the
more systems thinking you have to do.
(And it quite possibly runs the opposite direction as well, where the
more systems thinking you can/are able to do, the more it affects which ethical
approach you take.)
Second, I’ve been making an effort to point out the flaws in each
approach because it’s important to recognize where errors and biases can creep
into our own thinking. And that’s on top
of the fact that very few people rigidly fall into only one category; most
people change depending on circumstances, emotional effects, etc. We’re all very good at doing what they want
and then creating a justification afterwards.
And third, I’m not going to levy a judgment here on which approach is
best. (In fact, my goal is that, if you
didn’t already know where I fall, you’d be unable to tell from how I described
things.) To do so would actually
undermine the real point, which is this:
When it comes to ethics and morality, because we’re talking about
“good” and “bad”, “right” and “wrong”, it’s very easy to demonize the other
“side” just because they don’t think about things the same way you do. That’s part of why our politics are so
fractious right now: instead of trying to understand the other side, even if
you don’t agree with them, we just write them off as obtuse, clueless, or even
evil, just because they don’t approach life the way we do.
But that’s just the problem.
Someone whose entire framework of thinking and judging is different from
yours is inherently difficult to understand, because they’re making decisions
based on different priorities and philosophies than you. We want to look at things through our own
frameworks, and sometimes positions and decisions just won’t make sense to
us. And things like the fundamental
attribution error make us more likely to think that this is due to
something wrong with the other person.
I can’t tell you whether or not to throw the switch; all I can do is
trust you to make the decision you feel is right, even if it’s not the choice I
would make.
I don't think I could throw the switch.
ReplyDeleteI just realized this means I would make a horrible Vulcan...
DeleteEh. I think most people would be, and according to Star Trek that's not necessarily a bad thing.
ReplyDelete